Religious differences shaped not only the structures of learning and scholarship, but
also the content of thought in the sixteenth century, which was infl uenced as well by
the social and political changes we have traced in the previous two chapters. This can
be seen most clearly in political theory, which is often conceptualized in response to
actual political developments. Thus in the fourteenth century, after a series of confrontations
between the popes and various rulers, most political theory was concerned
with the proper relationship between church and state, with the balance shifting slowly
toward those who viewed secular government as having more legitimate authority.
Rulers were sanctioned by God, and their primary function was just like God’s: to
judge and protect those under their authority. In the early fi fteenth century, scholars in
Italian cities, which were often divided by political factions, taken over by home-grown
or regional despots, and attacked by foreign armies, looked to the stability of Rome as a
model state. Some of them, especially those infl uenced by the writings of Cicero, a fi rstcentury
bce Roman orator and opponent of Julius Caesar, argued that republicanism
was the best form of government. Others used the model of Plato’s philosopher-king in
the Republic to argue that rule by an enlightened single individual might be best. Both
sides agreed that educated men should be active in the political affairs of their city, a
position historians have since termed “civic humanism.”
The most famous (or infamous) civic humanist, and ultimately the best-known political
theorist of this era, was Niccolò Machiavelli. He was the secretary to one of the
governing bodies in the city of Florence, responsible for diplomatic missions and organizing
a citizen army. Power struggles in Florence between rival factions brought the
Medici family back to power, and Machiavelli was arrested, tortured, and imprisoned
on suspicion of plotting against them. He was released, but had no government position,
and spent the rest of his life writing – political theory, poetry, prose works, plays,
and a multivolume history of Florence. The fi rst work he fi nished – though it was not
the fi rst to be published – is his most famous, The Prince , which uses the example of
contemporary rulers, especially the papal general Cesare Borgia (1475?–1507), to argue
that the function of a ruler is to preserve order and security. Weakness would only lead
to disorder, which might end in civil war or conquest by an outsider, clearly situations
that were not conducive to any people’s well-being. To preserve the state a ruler should
use whatever means he needs – brutality, subterfuge, manipulation – but should not
do anything that would make the populace turn against him; stealing or cruel actions
done for a ruler’s own pleasure would only lead to resentment and destroy the popular
support needed for a strong, stable realm. “It is much safer for the prince to be feared
than loved,” Machiavelli advised, “but he ought to avoid making himself hated.” 3 Effective
rulers exhibited virtù , which is not virtue in the sense of moral goodness, but the
ability to shape the world around them according to their will.
METHODS AND ANALYSIS 3 Was Machiavelli Machiavellian?
Within forty years of Machiavelli’s death,
the word “Machiavellian” was applied to
individuals judged to be unscrupulous in
their methods of achieving a goal, and in
the seventeenth century, even his fi rst name
became a synonym for the devil, “Old Nick.”
Why was Machiavelli viewed so harshly?
Medieval political philosophers debated
the proper relationship between church and
state, but regarded the standards by which all
governments were to be judged as emanating
from moral principles established by God.
Machiavelli argued that governments should
instead be judged by how well they provided
security, order, and safety to their populace.
A ruler’s moral code in maintaining these was
not the same as a private individual’s, for a
leader could – indeed, should – use any means
necessary. This more pragmatic view of the
purposes of government, and Machiavelli’s
discussion of the role of force and cruelty, was
unacceptable to many.
The fact that Machiavelli was Italian also
became mixed in with these judgments. By the
sixteenth century, Italian merchants were often
resented in the same way that Jews had been
earlier, being regarded as unprincipled and
avaricious. Diplomacy was a new Italian invention,
viewed by many as centered on the clever use
of fl attery and deception. Italians served as
diplomats and advisors to rulers all over Europe,
but they were frequently accused of secret
dealings and plots, which at times escalated into
anti-Italian hysteria. The Italian advisor of Mary
Queen of Scots, for example, was stabbed to
death by Protestant nobles in 1566.
Not everyone agreed with this negative
view. Francis Bacon, the English scientist and
politician, praised Machiavelli for just what
others found so distasteful. “We are much
beholden to Machivel and others,” he wrote
in The Advancement of Learning (1605), “that
they write what men do, and not what they
ought to do” (bk II, xxi, 9). He quickly added,
“All good moral philosophy is but the handmaid
to religion” (bk II, xxii, 14), but this comment
may have been motivated by “Machiavellian”
expediency more than real sentiment.
In the eighteenth century, philosophers
and political leaders, including Jean-Jacques
Rousseau and John Adams, praised the ideas
about republicanism found in Machiavelli’s
other writings, and in the twentieth century
political thinkers with a range of views openly
drew on his ideas. “Machiavellian” continues
to be a term of criticism, however. Psychologists
use the phrase “Machiavellian intelligence” to
describe social skills that involve deception and
the ability to use cunning to form coalitions,
and journalists and political commentators
are never praising someone when they use
that word.
Cesare Borgia, Machiavelli’s primary example, was the son of Rodrigo Borgia, a
Spanish nobleman who became Pope Alexander VI (pontifi cate 1492–1503). Cesare
Borgia combined his father’s power and his own ruthlessness to build up a state in central
Italy. He made good use of new military equipment and tactics, hiring Leonardo da
Vinci (1452–1519) as a military engineer, and murdered his political enemies, including
one of the husbands of his sister, Lucrezia. Despite his efforts, after his father’s death his
state fell apart, which Machiavelli ascribed not to some weakness, but to the operations
of fate ( fortuna in Italian), whose power even the best-prepared and most merciless
ruler, the one with virtù , could not fully escape, though he might try.
Fortuna was personifi ed and portrayed as a goddess in ancient Rome and Renaissance
Italy, and Machiavelli’s last words about fortune are expressed in gendered terms: “It is
better to be impetuous than cautious, for fortune is a woman, and if one wishes to keep
her down, it is necessary to beat her and knock her down.” 4 Fate presented a new – and,
given Machiavelli’s words, one might even say ironic – challenge to both ruling houses
and political theorists in the sixteenth century. Though Machiavelli mentions only male
rulers by name, and virtù is linked conceptually and linguistically with vir (“man” in
Latin), dynastic accidents in many areas led to women serving as advisors to child kings
or ruling in their own right – Isabella in Castile, Mary and Elizabeth Tudor in England,
Anne in Brittany, Mary Stuart in Scotland, Mary of Guise, Catherine de’ Medici and
Anne of Austria in France. Theorists vigorously and at times viciously disputed whether
this was appropriate: could a woman’s being born into a royal family and educated to
rule allow her to overcome the limitations of her sex and become a successful ruler?
Should it? Or, stated another way: which was (or should be) the stronger determinant
of character and social role, gender or rank?
The most extreme opponents of female rule were Protestants who went into exile
on the continent during the reign of Mary Tudor, of whom the Scottish reformer John
Knox is the best known. In his The First Blast of the Trumpet Against the Monstrous
Regiment of Women (1558), Knox compared Mary Tudor and Mary Stuart to Jezebel,
arguing that female rule was unnatural, unlawful, monstrous, and contrary to Scripture;
being female was a condition that could never be overcome, and subjects of female
rulers needed no other justifi cation for rebelling than their monarch’s sex. Knox’s
work was published just as Elizabeth assumed the throne, however, and a number of
courtiers, including Thomas Smith and John Aylmer, realized that defenses of female
rule would be likely to help them win favor in Elizabeth’s eyes, and they advanced arguments
against viewing a woman’s sex as an absolute block to rulership.
Jean Bodin (1530?–96), the French jurist and political theorist, returned to Scripture
and natural law in his opposition to female rule in The Six Books of the Republic (1576),
but also stressed what would become in the seventeenth century the most frequently
cited reason against it: that the state was like a household, and just as in a household the
husband/father has authority and power over all others, so in the state a male monarch
should always rule. Robert Filmer carried this even further in Patriarchia , asserting that
rulers derived all legal authority from the divinely sanctioned fatherly power of Adam,
just as did all fathers. Male monarchs used husbandly and paternal imagery to justify
their assertion of power over their subjects, as in James I’s statements to Parliament: “I
am the Husband, and the whole Isle is my lawfull Wife … By the law of nature the king
becomes a natural father to all his lieges at his coronation … A King is trewly Parens
patriae , the politique father of his people.” 5
Bodin’s arguments in favor of male rule were shaped not only by the reality of female
monarchs, but also by the religious wars in France during the 1560s and 1570s.
(For more information about these, see chapter 5 .) Catholics and Protestants (called
Huguenots) engaged in military campaigns, plotted and carried out assassinations,
and sometimes massacred adherents of the other confession; the most brutal of these
was the St. Bartholomew’s Day Massacre in 1572, in which royal troops and Catholic
mobs killed thousands of Huguenots, fi rst in Paris and then in other French cities,
often mutilating the corpses afterwards. There is sharp debate among historians about
exactly who planned these killings, but after they were over the king admitted that he
ordered at least some of them, and those doing the killing clearly believed they were
doing the king’s will. In response, Protestant writers began to argue that the power of a
monarch should be limited, and that when a ruler became a tyrant, the people – or at
least those people who otherwise had some authority, such as offi ce-holders or representative
groups – had the right, or even the duty, to rebel. The most infl uential of these
works was the anonymous Defense of Liberty Against Tyrants (1579), probably written
by the Huguenot nobleman Philippe Duplessis de Mornay.
Bodin’s Six Books of the Republic was an answer to this resistance theory. For Bodin, all
political authority came from God, and kings were answerable to God alone; husband/
fathers had absolute authority in their households, but this never gave them the right to
resist, or even question, the actions of a divinely ordained monarch. To do so would lead
to anarchy, which was worse than the worst tyranny. Bodin’s opinions were not shared
by all Catholics, however. Radical Catholics later wrote their own resistance propaganda,
which actually authorized the regicide of a ruler judged to be ungodly. Resistance
theory on both sides was often written in very infl ammatory language and published in
pamphlet form, so that it was widely read.